The last decade has seen genetics and evolution grapple with its history; one composed of figures who laid the foundations of their field while also promoting vile racist, sexist, and eugenicist beliefs.
In her new book, The Genetic Lottery, Kathryn Paige Harden, professor of psychology at University of Texas at Austin, attempts the seemingly impossible task of showing that, despite a history of abuse, behavioral genetics is not only scientifically valuable but is an asset to the social justice movement.
In this attempt, she fails twice. For the first half of the book, Harden tries to transform the disappointment of behavioral genetics in the years following the Human Genome Project into a success that proves that genes are a major and important cause of social inequality, like educational attainment or income levels. In the second half, she tries to show that this information is not a justification for inequality, rather it is a tool to use in our efforts to make society more equitable and cannot be ignored if we wish to be successful. To say the least, this section too falls short. Harden refuses to engage with the history and trajectory of her field, and ultimately the science fails to uphold the idea that not considering genetic differences hinders our attempts to create a more equitable world.
In the book Misbehaving Science, sociologist Aaron Panofsky documents the history and progression of behavioral genetics, from its formal inception in the 1960s. Throughout its history behavioral genetics has responded to criticism in a variety of ways.
In 1969, the educational psychologist Arthur Jensen used behavioral genetics methods to argue that IQ gaps between white and Black Americans had genetic origins and, therefore, could not be remedied by educators or social policy. As criticism from mainstream geneticists and evolutionary biologists tied Jensen and behavioral geneticists to each other, the field attempted to hold a middle ground between Jensens racist conclusions and the belief that human behavioral genetics was fundamentally flawed. However, in this attempt to preserve their field from criticism, behavioral geneticists progressively defended the importance of race science research and adopted some core premises about the influence of genetic differences on the racial IQ gap.
In the following decades, Jensen and like-minded researchers like J. Philippe Rushton, Richard Lynn, and Linda Gottfredson received funding from the Pioneer Fund, an organization explicitly dedicated to race betterment. All the while, they were integrated into editorial boards of journals that published behavioral genetics work and treated as colleagues. Even mainstream behavioral genetics work like the Minnesota Study of Twins Reared Apart and the Texas Adoption Project would receive funding from the noxious Fund.
In attempts to justify their field against continued criticism, behavioral geneticists themselves used twin study results to argue social interventions would be ineffective. As Panofsky wrote:
This history, including behavioral genetics' own role in generating, promoting, and defending scientific racism and determinist views of genetics is completely absent from Harden's book. This history matters; it is the source of the isolation of behavioral genetics from mainstream genetics research. This isolation has produced the intellectual and ideologically stagnant lineage that Harden operates in.
These biases are most pronounced in the early chapters walking readers through the science, which often leads to an incomplete, misleading, or mistaken account of genetic research and behavior. Harden presents an argument about the major causal role of genetic differences. These results span decades, including twin studies, and recent developments like genome-wide association studies (GWAS), polygenic scores (a single value combining individual estimated effects of genome-wide variations on a phenotype), and genomic analyses of siblings. Unfortunately, Harden often gives these results in such a misleading way that it obscures how damaging they actually are to her own core thesis.
For example, Harden extols sibling analyses as unassailable evidence of independent, direct genetic causation free of biases found in other methods. While its true that polygenic scores from sibling analyses resolve substantial problems that sometimes create inaccurate associations between DNA and a phenotype, Harden fails to mention several key differences between these sibling-based methods and other genomic or twin-based methods. It is rarely stated clearly that these family methods produce much smaller estimates of genetic effect, often nearly half the size as population-based methods, making the 13% variance explained by current education polygenic scores a likely overestimate. Harden also fails to mention that a commonly used method employed does not fully eliminate the problems from population structure or that estimates from siblings can still include confounding effects that create correlations between genes and environment.
Even worse, Harden moves between the less biased, but smaller, results from sibling methods to the more biased but larger estimates from population-based polygenic scores without being clear this is what she is doing. This happens frequently when discussing research claiming that educational polygenic scores substantially explain differences in income. The result is Harden obscures the fact that more reliable techniques result in lower predicted genetic effects. Readers may be wrongfully led to believe genetic effects are both large and reliable when in reality they are more often one or the other.
Hardens failure to engage with critics of behavioral genetics, often from the political left, veers between simple omissions and outright misrepresentation. This treatment is in stark contrast to how she treats biological determinists on the political right. The work of Charles Murray, the co-author of The Bell Curve, which claimed that differences in IQ scores between the rich and poor were genetic, and whose research aligns neatly with Hardens, is described as mostly true and his political implications are lightly challenged. The most prominent critic of behavioral genetics, Richard Lewontin, gets much rougher treatment.
In one of the three cases in which Harden bothers to mention Lewontins decades-long engagement with behavioral genetics, she gets it wrong, claiming that Lewontin merely said that heritability is useless because it is specific to a particular population at a particular time. In reality, Lewontin showed why the statistical foundation of heritability analyses means it is unable to truly separate genetic and environmental effects. Contra Hardens characterization of her opponents, Lewontin recognized genetic factors as a cause of phenotypes; however, he stressed their effects cannot be independent of environmental factors and the dynamics of development.
Harden implies that giving people access to equal resources increases inequality and genetic influence. Lewontin explained why the outcome of equalizing environments precisely depends on which environment you equalize. As a toy example, a cactus and a rose bush respond differently to varying amounts of water. Giving both plants the same, small, volume of water is good for the cactuss health and bad for the rose, giving both a larger volume of water is bad for the cactus and good for the rose. Equalized environments regardless of quality can reduce or increase inequality and can reduce or increase the impact of genotypic differences depending on the environment and the norm of reaction for a trait and set of genotypes. Heritability analyses cannot provide insight on this distribution or nature of genotype and environment interactions. These detailed, quantitative, and analytic arguments are entirely ignored by Harden.
In her story, people on the political left are ideologically driven to oppose behavioral genetics because they believe it invalidates their desire to ameliorate inequality. In the powerful book-length criticism of behavioral genetics, Not in Our Genes, Lewontin, with neuroscientist Steven Rose and psychologist Leon Kamin, all socialists, defy Hardens characterization of her critics from the left, writing:
They further write:
Not in Our Genes criticizes biological determinism for oversimplifying the processes that create diversity in the natural world. And the ways that biological determinism is employed for political and ideological reasons by people like Arthur Jensen, Daniel Patrick Moynihan, or Hans Eysenck, to undermine movements for social and economic equality on the basis of biological data. Lewontin, Kamin, and Rose did not oppose biological determinism simply on ideological grounds. They knew there was no true threat to egalitarian beliefs posed by biological data if one properly understands biology in a non-determinist way. Instead, they wanted to move beyond just a scientific critique and provide a social analysis of why the mistakes of biological determinism are made, persist, and gain in popularity. They write:
This lack of meaningful engagement with critics is not just poor scholarship, it weakens Hardens case. Problems arise with Hardens discussion of heritability, for example, which would be remedied with a genuine engagement with critics from mainstream genetics and evolutionary biology. Harden takes a hardline position that heritability is a measure of genetic causation within a sampled population; however, despite her attempt over two chapters to build this case, she is still fundamentally mistaken about the concept.
Early work in plant breeding and genetics can help shed light on the source of this confusion. The pre-eminent statistical geneticist, Oscar Kempthorne, in a 1978 critique of behavioral genetics, wrote that the methods employed by the field can tell us nothing about causation because all they really represent is simply a linear association between genetics and phenotypes, without any further ability to connect the two to each other.
The extent to which correlations can be interpreted as causation depends on properly controlling for confounding variables. In the context of heritability, this means that genetics and environment need to be independent of each other, but this cannot be the case without direct experimental manipulation. In fields like plant breeding, it is possible to experimentally randomize which environments a plant genotype experiences, and genetically identical plants can be put in different environments for extra control, so these inferences are safer to make. In human genetics, however, this is not possible even with the sibling and twin methods Harden focuses on. These processes that complicate causal interpretation of heritability estimates have been discussed ad nauseum by other behavioral geneticists, which is why Harden is one of the few who comes to her conclusions.
One final glaring omission worth noting occurs in Hardens chapter on race and findings of behavioral genetics. Here, Harden does an admirable job trying to prevent the misapplication of behavioral genetics to questions of racial differences. Surprisingly absent though is the fact that across a variety of studies, genetic variation is much larger within races compared to between races. This finding undermines core perceptions about the biological nature and significance of race. It also has important implications for our assumptions about the role of genetics in phenotypic differences between races, namely that they will be small to nonexistent. One could speculate the omission is because the finding was from none other than Richard Lewontin. This case is particularly problematic because in randomized control trials, biology classes emphasizing Lewontins findings have shown very strong evidence of reducing racial essentialism, prejudice, and stereotyping. Few science education interventions against racism and prejudice have such strong evidence in their favor.
Above all, Harden desperately wants to impart one idea in the first part of the book: genes cause social inequality. Here she argues for causation as differences makers in counterfactual scenarios. In other words, X causes Y if the probability of Y occurring is different were X not to happen. As Harden notes, experimental science adopts a similar and in ways stronger, interventionist theory of causation, based around experimental interventions. Here X is said to cause Y if there is a regular response of Y to an intervention on X.
Under the interventionist theory, Hardens account of genetic causation runs into trouble. First, it requires us to be able to isolate a specific property on which we can intervene. This is possible in cases of simple genetic disorders with clear biological mechanisms and short pathways from gene to trait, like sickle cell anemia or Tay-Sachs. However, this doesnt work for behaviorally- and culturally-mediated traits involving large numbers of genes, with small effects and diffuse associations between genetic and non-genetic factors. There is simply no method to isolate and intervene on the effects of specific genetic variants that holds environmental factors constant in a way we would normally recognize as an experimental intervention. This applies still to the sibling analyses that Harden tries to portray as randomization experiments. Contrary to one of Hardens more bizarre claims, meiosis does not approximate a randomized experiment. All it does is randomize genotypes with respect to siblings, it does not randomize environments experienced by genotypes. Our broad array of social and cultural institutions still acts in a confounding way. Instead, we just have a polygenic score, which is more a statistical construct than a tangible property in the world.
Second, for Hardens causal claims to hold weight, genetic and environmental factors must be distinct components that are independently disruptable. This reflects what the philosopher John Stuart Mill called the principle of the composition of causes, which states that the joint effect of several causes is identical with the sum of their separate effects. At the core, Harden assumes that genetic and environmental influences on human behavior are independent and separable. To say the absolute least, this is a highly dubious assumption. Based on the arguments from critics like Lewontin and the work from research programs like developmental systems theory, there is very good reason to think that biological systems are not modular, especially in the case of educational attainment. Genetic and environmental influences interact throughout development, the interactions are dynamic, reciprocal, and highly contingent. It simply isnt plausible to estimate the independent effect of one or the other because they directly influence each other.
A further weakness of Hardens book is that just because genes make a difference in phenotype, it does not mean that genes are even relevant to the analysis of these phenotypes. In reality, Lewiss account of causation, that X is a cause if a different outcome would have occurred in the absence of X, can be a pretty low bar, and the causes it identified may not be very relevant. An obviously absurd example is that the argument could be made that the sun caused me to wake up this morning since it is the origin of the trophic cascade that nourished my body enough to continue necessary biological functions. Under Lewis account, the sun is a cause of my waking up, but its hardly a relevant or informative cause compared to my alarm clock or to the bus I need to catch at 8:35am.
In Biology as Ideology, Lewontin discusses the causes of the disease tuberculosis. He notes that in medical textbooks the tubercle bacillus, which gives people the disease when infected, is the cause of tuberculosis. Lewontin writes that this biological explanation is focused on the individual level and treats the biological sphere as independent from external causes related to the environment or social structure. While we can surely talk about the role of the tubercle bacillus in causing the disease we can also talk about the social conditions of unregulated industrial capitalism and its role in causing outbreaks and deaths by tuberculosis and can gain far more insight by analyzing the causes of tuberculosis in that way.
This distinction of whether a cause is relevant for particular social and scientific issues becomes a problem for Harden in the climax of her book where she tries to convince the reader that genetic information is a crucial tool for addressing social inequality.
One example given by Harden is that children who perform well but are in poor schools are able to achieve less, and that poor people with higher education end up making less money than rich people in the same fields. These findings are neither novel nor do they require the use of potentially misleading genetic data. While Harden tries to defuse right-wing arguments about shortcomings of social science research, this isnt a given. As research Harden herself presents shows, results from behavioral genetics bolster the far right and they regularly share this research to promote their beliefs and challenge egalitarian policies. Instead of engaging with this bad-faith criticism from the right, we can simply disregard them, just as Harden disregards their co-option of her field of research.
Finally, Harden expresses a general concern that social science and psychological studies are plagued by genetic confounding, that is the correlations they observe are actually due to unconsidered genetic forces that relate an individual to their outcome (i.e. low income doesnt cause poor health, genes cause both low income and poor health). For this example, Harden is hard on these complaints, equating research that does not include genetic information as tantamount to robbing taxpayers, but light on evidence that this genetic confounding is a widespread problem, or that it can only be addressed with behavioral genetic research.
Surprisingly, all these examples abandon the earlier bluster about genes being crucial causal factors in our life and instead opt for genetic data as one of many methods for causal inference of environmental interventions. We no longer care about heritability estimates; instead, we use twins as an experimental design. In some cases this is fine, however using individuals who have similar genotype, environmental characteristics, and phenotype does not mean that genes are significant causes, its just a good experimental design. Here, some of Hardens arguments about social science research are accurate. Observational and correlation-based studies are weak for a number of reasons, not simply because they ignore genetic differences. The goal should be strengthening causal inference in the social sciences, and we have some idea of how to do that from other fields. To strengthen the ability to identify causes, epidemiologists employ direct experiments, like randomized control trials, exploit natural experiments that can approximate experimental randomization, such as studies that observe changes in outcome shortly after changes in government policy are enacted, or designs that use statistical methods to match people based on background demographic information like income, neighborhood quality, family education, etc.
In fact, there are principled reasons to think genetic data has little to no benefit above and beyond the kinds of data we can collect from non-genetic social science experiments. Eric Turkheimer, Hardens doctoral advisor, has articulated the phenotypic null hypothesis which states that for many behavioral traits the genetic variance identified from behavioral genetics studies is not an independent mechanism of individual differences and instead reflects deeply intertwined developmental processes that are best understood and studied at the level of the phenotype. This certainly appears to hold for the traits Harden talks about. Even with GWAS and polygenic scores, we are given no coherent biological mechanism beyond...something to do with the brain, they interact with and are correlated with the environment, and they are contextual and modifiable. Harden laments focus on mechanisms, but identifying specific causal mechanisms would be precisely how education polygenic scores could be actually helpful. For example, in medicine, GWAS have helped identify potential drug targets by identifying biological mechanisms of disease, and can double the likelihood of a drug making it through clinical trials.
However, this situation doesnt exist for things like education. Instead, we can understand the role of correlated traits like ADHD, or the effect of interventions purely at the phenotypic level by seeing how educational performance and attainment itself change upon interventions from well-designed experiments. In fact, several polygenic scores, from educational attainment to schizophrenia, and even diseases like cardiovascular disease have been shown to have virtually no predictive power beyond common clinical or phenotypic measures, meaning we do not more accurately predict the outcome of those particular phenotypes even with robust polygenic scores. So why not focus our efforts on phenotypes instead of genotypes in cases like education, income, and health where we have some ability to do randomized experiments and a wealth of quasi-natural experiments?
There are existing studies that attempt some kind of true experimental manipulation related to education. Despite what Harden or the charter-school supporting billionaire John Arnold says, we do have some idea on what can improve schools. Research indicates that de-tracking education, that is ending the separation of students by academic ability and having all students engage in challenging curriculum, regularly improves student performance for those with lower ability and does not hinder students with higher ability.
Experiments have shown large benefits to those passing classes and the grades they receive when courses are structured around a more pedagogically informed curriculum that actively engages students. Detracking and active learning have the added advantage of greatly affecting racial gaps in educational performance. To achieve these goals it is likely that teachers will need to be better trained and compensated, and student-pupil ratios would need to change. These changes would likely be related to school funding, teacher salary and quality, and school resources even if those factors are not sufficient to improve educational outcomes in every situation.
Simply identifying that other methods can improve social sciences doesnt mean we shouldnt use every tool in our toolbox, as Harden says. However, there are convincing reasons we ought not to rely on genetic data for this kind of research. One reason is that polygenic scores are not very good as controls for experiments testing the effect of environmental intervention. Research has found that the pervasive interplay of genes and environment weakens their ability to control for genetic confounding or identify the efficacy of environmental interventions. Since polygenic scores can reflect contingent social biases without us knowing, it is possible, and likely, that by relying on them to identify effective interventions we are in fact reifying ingrained social and economic biases further in our systems.
One final concern is how this research is interpreted by people, were it to be widely adopted. Researchers found in online experiments that the very act of classifying someone based on their educational polygenic score led to stigmas and self-fulfilling prophecies. Those with high scores were perceived to have more potential and competence while those with low scores were perceived in the opposite way. Not only does this research suggest genetic data leads to essentialist beliefs that can re-entrench existing inequalities, but this kind of dependency can also create even more confounding influences that complicate the application of genetic data for social science questions.
Finally, we reach the last issue with The Genetic Lottery: we dont need the concept of genetic luck to pursue egalitarian policies. Harden regularly remarks that the alternative is to perceive peoples outcomes as their individual responsibility. Either something is the result of genes they have no control over, or it is their fault for not working hard enough. However, progressive politics revolves around structural and systemic factors that are outside of peoples control and contribute to their outcomes. There is already a recognition of moral luck, or that peoples outcomes are not their fault, but due to the situations they find themselves in. This engagement with progressive motivations and philosophy is absent in Hardens analysis.
In Hardens penultimate chapter she contrasts eugenic, genome-blind, and anti-eugenic approaches to policy. What ultimately occurs is a strawman of genome-blind policy approaches and often anti-eugenic policies that are hard to distinguish from eugenic policies. For example, what is the difference between Hardens description of the eugenic policy Classify people into social roles or positions based on their genetics and the anti-eugenic policy Use genetic data to maximize the real capabilities of people to achieve social roles and positions? While the genome-blind position is described as Pretend that all people have an equal likelihood of achieving all social roles or positions after taking into account their environment., all we really need to do to achieve our progressive goals is ensure that peoples ability to succeed and thrive in life is not conditioned upon their origin, preferences, or abilities. Theres simply no need to use genetic data on people at all.
In another case involving healthcare Harden suggests the genome-blind approach is to keep our system the same while prohibiting the use of genetic information, while the anti-eugenic approach is creating systems where everyone is included, regardless of the outcome of the genetic lottery. However, the system Harden describes is not universal social programs that ensure healthcare, housing, or education regardless of economic situations. Rather it is a system that resembles means-testing social welfare with genetic data. Of course, universal social programs do achieve exactly the anti-eugenic goal while still being genome-blind! Hardens complete disregard for actual rationale and form of progressive policies when crafting the genome-blind caricatures is inexcusable from someone who claims to be progressive.
For a progressive that supports universal healthcare, a living wage for all, housing as a human right, or free education, it does not matter that people are different and it does not matter the cause for that difference. The fact that some people need healthcare to survive is the reason why it should be available for free, whether the need is from an inherited or acquired disease. It is acknowledged that people have different preferences and strengths, which ultimately results in them living different lives. The fact that for some people this means the difference between a living wage and poverty is what progressives take issue with, and it doesnt matter what the cause of these differences are, simply that we address them.
Ultimately, Harden tries to sell us on research that we dont need, based on faulty premises, and that is incapable of delivering on what she promises. Her failure to engage with the history of her own field, her scientific critics, or the actual content of progressive political goals leaves this book in a very poor place. In a way, The Genetic Lottery represents the fact that behavioral genetics no longer has a place to go after the tenets of genetic determinism and biological reductionism were shown to be untenable. If one wants to gain an understanding of modern genetics, or to learn how we may strengthen progressive causes, they should look elsewhere.
Follow this link:
The Genetic Lottery is a bust for both genetics and policy - Massive Science
- Toward advances in retinoblastoma genetics in Kenya - Nature.com - November 12th, 2024 [November 12th, 2024]
- CRISPR/Cas9 screens identify key host factors that enhance rotavirus reverse genetics efficacy and vaccine production - Nature.com - November 12th, 2024 [November 12th, 2024]
- Genetics Play Key Role in Animal Health and Welfare, Aggression and Handling - Farms.com - November 12th, 2024 [November 12th, 2024]
- Episode 174: Rudy Tanzi talks about genetics, aging and the hallmarks of Alzheimers - IHMC - October 26th, 2024 [October 26th, 2024]
- Ocuphire and Opus Genetics merge to develop IRD gene therapy - Pharmaceutical Technology - October 26th, 2024 [October 26th, 2024]
- The RD Fund Announces Ocuphire Pharma's Acquisition of Opus Genetics - PR Newswire - October 26th, 2024 [October 26th, 2024]
- The RD Fund Announces Ocuphire Pharma's Acquisition of Opus Genetics - WV News - October 26th, 2024 [October 26th, 2024]
- Faculty of Science | Protecting Canadas number one crop through genetics - UM Today - October 26th, 2024 [October 26th, 2024]
- Ocuphire and Opus Genetics merge to develop IRD gene therapy - Yahoo Finance - October 26th, 2024 [October 26th, 2024]
- Opinion | Fascinated by genetics? Where are the peas Trump made to fornicate? - The Washington Post - October 13th, 2024 [October 13th, 2024]
- Dietary restriction can extend lifespan but genetics matters more - Nature.com - October 13th, 2024 [October 13th, 2024]
- 'They have much stronger players' - Bangladesh assistant coach bizarrely blames 'genetics' for lack of six hitters in the team - Sporting News - October 13th, 2024 [October 13th, 2024]
- Medical Moment: Genetics and breast cancer with USA Health Genetic Counselor Cassie Gurganus - AOL - October 13th, 2024 [October 13th, 2024]
- Myriad Genetics Announces Five Research Collaborations to Study the Use of MRD Testing in Breast Cancer - Yahoo Finance - October 13th, 2024 [October 13th, 2024]
- An ideologically-based and misleading critique of how modern genetics is taught - Why Evolution Is True - October 13th, 2024 [October 13th, 2024]
- 2024 Mercedes-AMG C63 Review: Bold But Beholden to Its Genetics - Newsweek - October 2nd, 2024 [October 2nd, 2024]
- Myriad Genetics Announces Third Patent Granted for Molecular Residual Disease (MRD) with Early Priority Date - GlobeNewswire - October 2nd, 2024 [October 2nd, 2024]
- Digbi Health Launches an SEC-regulated Offering, Giving Millions the Opportunity to Invest in Groundbreaking Genetics and Gut Microbiome-based Care... - October 2nd, 2024 [October 2nd, 2024]
- The role of genetics in depression | Second Opinion - KCRW - September 23rd, 2024 [September 23rd, 2024]
- Tilapia genetics company Spring Genetics teams up with UK data firm to improve fish welfare - SeafoodSource - September 23rd, 2024 [September 23rd, 2024]
- Picky eating in kids is mostly due to genetics, study says - Motherly Inc. - September 23rd, 2024 [September 23rd, 2024]
- Research Shows That Fussy Eating In Children Is Mainly Influenced By Genetics - RTTNews - September 23rd, 2024 [September 23rd, 2024]
- Genetics colloquium: Chris Hittinger on the genomic making of metabolic niche breadth Sep. 11 - University of WisconsinMadison - September 15th, 2024 [September 15th, 2024]
- NIH Recognizes Yales Expertise in the Genetics of Rare Diseases - Yale School of Medicine - September 15th, 2024 [September 15th, 2024]
- SOPHiA GENETICS and AstraZeneca Collaborate to Further Expand Global Access to Liquid Biopsy Testing - PR Newswire - September 15th, 2024 [September 15th, 2024]
- Medicines race dilemma: What science says about genetics and health [PODCAST] - Kevin MD - September 15th, 2024 [September 15th, 2024]
- Researchers want to unlock genetics of the worlds tiniest animals - Popular Science - September 15th, 2024 [September 15th, 2024]
- Sophia Genetics and AstraZeneca collaborate to expand liquid biopsy test rollout - Medical Device Network - September 15th, 2024 [September 15th, 2024]
- From farm to future: Technology in genetics - National Hog Farmer - September 2nd, 2024 [September 2nd, 2024]
- Editorial: Plant biotechnology and genetics for sustainable agriculture and global food security - Frontiers - September 2nd, 2024 [September 2nd, 2024]
- NSF Grant Brings Genetics Opportunities to Students in Alabama - Government Technology - September 2nd, 2024 [September 2nd, 2024]
- SBUs Ben Luft brings Lyme expertise to seminal paper on bacterial genetics and evolution - TBR News Media - September 2nd, 2024 [September 2nd, 2024]
- SOPHiA GENETICS to Present at the 22nd Annual Morgan Stanley Healthcare Conference and 9th Annual TD Cowen FutureHealth Conference - PR Newswire - September 2nd, 2024 [September 2nd, 2024]
- Singapores National Precision Medicine (NPM) Programme Engages Oxford Nanopore to Advance Understanding of the Genetics of Singapores Multi-Ethnic... - August 5th, 2024 [August 5th, 2024]
- Fulgent Genetics Second Quarter 2024 Earnings: Beats Expectations - Yahoo Finance - August 5th, 2024 [August 5th, 2024]
- Stopped clinical trials give evidence for the value of genetics - Nature.com - August 5th, 2024 [August 5th, 2024]
- What is DSD? Sex genetics and Olympic boxing controversy - Washington Examiner - August 5th, 2024 [August 5th, 2024]
- Fulgent Genetics Q2: Core Revenue Grows, but Profitability Is Still an Issue - The Motley Fool - August 5th, 2024 [August 5th, 2024]
- Viewpoint: Challenging yet another scientifically silly article claiming Black domination of sprinting and long distance running has nothing to do... - August 5th, 2024 [August 5th, 2024]
- Texas Company Trying To Resurrect Woolly Mammoths To Improve Genetics Of Bison - Cowboy State Daily - August 5th, 2024 [August 5th, 2024]
- Genetics confirms Berbers reached North Africa over 20,000 years ago; Arabs came in 7th Century CE - Down To Earth Magazine - August 5th, 2024 [August 5th, 2024]
- Unlocking plant genetics with telomere-to-telomere genome assemblies - Nature.com - July 26th, 2024 [July 26th, 2024]
- Carlo Ancelotti claims Jude Bellingham's 'genetics' are main reason behind Real Madrid & England superstar's meteoric rise to the top - Goal.com - July 26th, 2024 [July 26th, 2024]
- Genetics-based modeling estimates Idaho's wolf population was 1,150 in summer 2023 - Idaho Fish and Game - July 26th, 2024 [July 26th, 2024]
- Lung Cancer Research Foundation Joins Lung Cancer Advocacy Organizations and 23andMe to Launch Lung Cancer Genetics Study to Advance Research - PR... - July 26th, 2024 [July 26th, 2024]
- Fulgent Genetics (FLGT) Scheduled to Post Earnings on Friday - Defense World - July 26th, 2024 [July 26th, 2024]
- SOPHIA GENETICS Announces Expanded Relationship with Canada-Based OncoHelix - Financial Times - July 26th, 2024 [July 26th, 2024]
- LG Household & Health Care publishes research into the genetics of skin tone - GlobalCosmeticsNews - July 26th, 2024 [July 26th, 2024]
- Estonians gave their DNA to science now they're learning their genetic secrets - Nature.com - June 27th, 2024 [June 27th, 2024]
- Genetic clues to depression revealed in large study - PsyPost - June 27th, 2024 [June 27th, 2024]
- Move Over, Genghis Khan. Many Other Men Left Huge Genetic Legacies - Smithsonian Magazine - June 27th, 2024 [June 27th, 2024]
- 3X4 Genetics Selected as Partner for Preeminent Cancer Research and Treatment Nonprofit, The Metabolic Terrain ... - BioSpace - June 27th, 2024 [June 27th, 2024]
- NIFA Invests $6M in Animal Breeding, Genetics and Genomics | NIFA - National Institute of Food and Agriculture - June 27th, 2024 [June 27th, 2024]
- Arbel Harpak: Pursuing the Next Frontier in Genetics | Dell Medical School - Dell Medical School - June 27th, 2024 [June 27th, 2024]
- Coffee habits are partly linked to genetics, UC San Diego researchers say - NBC San Diego - June 27th, 2024 [June 27th, 2024]
- Advanced genetic tools help researchers ID new neurodevelopmental syndrome - Yale News - June 27th, 2024 [June 27th, 2024]
- Nutritious diet may protect against type 2 diabetes, regardless of genetics - News-Medical.Net - June 27th, 2024 [June 27th, 2024]
- Genome-wide association study identifies host genetic variants influencing oral microbiota diversity and metabolic ... - Nature.com - June 27th, 2024 [June 27th, 2024]
- Unlock the Secrets of Your DNA with Advanced Genetic Testing - North Forty News - June 27th, 2024 [June 27th, 2024]
- Modern and precise: Using gene editing to change the blueprint of an organism - Beef Magazine - June 27th, 2024 [June 27th, 2024]
- The 'gene deserts' unravelling the mysteries of disease - BBC.com - June 27th, 2024 [June 27th, 2024]
- UGA plant geneticists are tackling the climate crisis - Longview News-Journal - June 27th, 2024 [June 27th, 2024]
- Genetic Tests for Predicting Clopidogrel Response Gain Traction: AHA - TCTMD - June 27th, 2024 [June 27th, 2024]
- Bringing Gene Therapy to the Brain - The Scientist - June 27th, 2024 [June 27th, 2024]
- The importance of the paradise fish in evolutionary and behavioral genetics research - Phys.org - June 9th, 2024 [June 9th, 2024]
- What Is Fulgent Genetics, Inc.'s (NASDAQ:FLGT) Share Price Doing? - Yahoo Finance - June 9th, 2024 [June 9th, 2024]
- UW initiative aims to bring together social sciences and genetics - Wisbusiness.com - June 9th, 2024 [June 9th, 2024]
- Women have a higher genetic risk for PTSD, according to study by VCU and Swedish researchers - VCU News - June 9th, 2024 [June 9th, 2024]
- Genetics study points to potential treatments for restless leg syndrome - University of Cambridge news - June 9th, 2024 [June 9th, 2024]
- deCODE genetics: The rate, nature and transmission of mitochondrial DNA mutations in humans - PR Newswire - June 9th, 2024 [June 9th, 2024]
- Genetic association mapping leveraging Gaussian processes | Journal of Human Genetics - Nature.com - June 9th, 2024 [June 9th, 2024]
- Minimally destructive hDNA extraction method for retrospective genetics of pinned historical Lepidoptera specimens ... - Nature.com - June 9th, 2024 [June 9th, 2024]
- Restless legs syndrome tied to 140 'hotspots' in the genome - Livescience.com - June 9th, 2024 [June 9th, 2024]
- Paired tumor-germline testing can enhance patient carewith guidance from genetics specialists - The Cancer Letter - June 9th, 2024 [June 9th, 2024]
- Improved functional mapping of complex trait heritability with GSA-MiXeR implicates biologically specific gene sets - Nature.com - June 9th, 2024 [June 9th, 2024]
- Genetic Risk Score Revolutionizes TNBC Prediction in Black Women - Targeted Oncology - June 9th, 2024 [June 9th, 2024]
- Gene variants and breast cancer risk in Black women - National Institutes of Health (NIH) (.gov) - June 9th, 2024 [June 9th, 2024]
- GSA-MiXeR: A powerful tool to improve our understanding of heritable traits and diseases - News-Medical.Net - June 9th, 2024 [June 9th, 2024]
- Understanding the effect genetics have on Alzheimer's - Buffalo News - June 9th, 2024 [June 9th, 2024]
- 'Fossil viruses' embedded in the human genome linked to psychiatric disorders - Livescience.com - June 9th, 2024 [June 9th, 2024]