CONVERSATIONS IN CRITICAL PSYCHIATRY
Conversations in Critical Psychiatry is an interview series aimed to engage prominent critics within and outside the profession who have made meaningful criticisms of psychiatry and have offered constructive alternative perspectives to the current status quo.
Joanna Moncrieff, MD, is Professor of Critical and Social Psychiatry at University College London and works as a consultant in community psychiatry in London. She has researched and written about theories of drug action, drug efficacy, the subjective experience of taking psychiatric drugs; decision-making; the history of drug treatment; and the history, politics, and philosophy of psychiatry more generally. She is currently leading a UK government-funded study of antipsychotic reduction and discontinuation, called the RADAR study (Research into Antipsychotic Discontinuation and Reduction). She is one of the founders and the co-chairperson of the Critical Psychiatry Network. She has authored numerous papers and several books including The Myth of the Chemical Cure (Palgrave Macmillan, 2008); The Bitterest Pills: The Troubling Story of Antipsychotic Drugs (Palgrave Macmillan, 2013); and A Straight-Talking Introduction to Psychiatric Drugs (PCCS Publishers, 2013).
Dr Moncrieff s views on psychopharmacological mechanisms of action, although controversial, have been influential within the critical psychiatry community. We have discussed some implications of the drug-centered model in an earlier interview with Dr Steingard. Dr Moncrieff s ongoing randomized controlled trial investigating the long-term impact of gradual antipsychotic dose reduction and discontinuation in schizophrenia on outcomes such as psychotic relapse and social functioning (versus maintenance treatment) can potentially alter how the field approaches management of chronic psychotic disorders.
This interview, however, largely focuses on conceptual concerns, exploring her views on the nature of psychiatric suffering. My first conscious exposure to Dr Moncrieff was at the 2017 annual meeting of the Association for the Advancement of Philosophy and Psychiatry, where Dr. Moncrieff gave the keynote lecture titled Many Ways of Being Human, in which she challenged the medical view of mental disorders and argued that medical and psychiatric conditions have a different relationship to agency, responsibility, and selfhood.
Dr Moncrieff s ideas represent in many ways the enduring legacy of Thomas Szasz and given my own disagreements with how Szasz conceptualizes the notion of disease, this interview also represents an attempt on my part to understand how deep our philosophical disagreements go.
Aftab: Can you briefly tell us about the Critical Psychiatry Network? How was it created, what is its mission, and how do you think Critical Psychiatry Network has impacted British psychiatry over the years?
Moncrieff: When I was a trainee in psychiatry, I felt the way psychiatry was portrayed in the mainstreamin textbooks and medical journalsdid not match my ideas about the nature of mental health problems or my experience of people who were deemed to have such problems. I was aware that other trainees felt like this too, so I started a club while I was at the Institute of Psychiatry in 1997. Initially we had discussions about interesting books and articles, and then we organized meetings, in conjunction with the Maudsley hospital service users group, with outside speakers, including the likes of Thomas Szasz, Nikolas Rose and Andrew Scull.
Around this time, we were contacted by some psychiatrists from another part of the UK, who were concerned about the upcoming review of the Mental Health Act. We got together to submit evidence to this review and that was the start of the Critical Psychiatry Network. Since that time, it has functioned as a forum for mutual support, and as a mechanism for contributing a critical view of psychiatric practice to various parliamentary and governmental reviews, the media and other organizations. Have we had any impact? I think the fact that members of the psychiatric profession are challenging mainstream views, particularly the dominance of the biological paradigm in psychiatry, is important, and helps to support broader movements that are trying to imagine and establish alternative approaches.
Aftab: Models of drug action have been an important focus of your work, in particular, the distinction between disease centered model and drug centered model. In the disease centered model, drugs help correct an abnormal brain state and the therapeutic effects of drugs are derived from their effects on an underlying disease process. In the drug centered model, drugs are psychoactive agents that create an abnormal brain state, and therapeutic effects are derived from the impact of drug-induced state on behavioral and emotional problems. Can you elaborate for us how ignoring this has distorted our understanding of the treatment of psychiatric conditions and has biased our assessments of risks and benefits?
Moncrieff: Assuming that drugs work by acting on the underlying biological mechanisms of mental symptoms (the disease-centered model) has obscured the fact that the drugs we use in psychiatry are psychoactive drugsthat is, drugs that change the brain in ways we do not fully understand and by doing so produce more or less subtle alterations to normal mental experiences and behaviorwhat I have called the drug-centered model of drug action. Because we have ignored the fact that psychiatric drugs are psychoactive substances, we have not bothered to properly research or even describe the physical and mental physical alterations they produce and all the short and long-term consequences of these. Therefore, we are not making fully informed assessments of the benefits and harms of drug treatment, and because we assume we are rectifying an underlying abnormality, we tend to over-estimate the benefits of treatment and understate its harms.
So although I think there are some situations in which some drugs can be useful (antipsychotics in acute psychosis, benzodiazepines in acute agitation, for example), this has led, in my view, to a situation in which millions of people world-wide are taking drugs that are doing them little or no good, but are causing them harmboth harm that we know about and harm that we have not properly researched yet.
Aftab: I wonder if the disease centered model conflates instances of disease processes with biological mechanisms. Let s consider a thought experiment. Assume that in patient A, biological mechanism X mediates, in part, the subjective experience of anhedonia. We are not qualifying mechanism X as an abnormality or disease, we are simply saying that it is a mechanism, among other mechanisms, of generating anhedonia. Now patient A takes a medication M, and M has a direct action on X leads to an improvement in anhedonia. Again, we are not saying that medication M is fixing an abnormality in X, just that it has a direct action on mechanism X. In this thought experiment, the medication M is neither correcting a disease process nor is it producing a therapeutic effect indirectly from a drug induced state; it is producing a therapeutic effect by a direct action on a mechanism that is not necessarily abnormal but is nonetheless directly involved in the experience being targeted. How would your framework incorporate such hypotheticals?
Moncrieff: I think I make it clear in my writings that the disease-centered model I have outlined is not restricted to what we think of as diseases, especially as the use of this term in psychiatry is not clear-cut. The disease-centered model consists of the idea that drugs work by targeting underlying biological mechanisms that produce what we call the symptoms of mental disorders. Hence your thought experiment is an example of the disease-centered model as I have formulated it.
My response to your example is this: First of all, we have no idea what biological mechanism mediates anhedonia or almost any other subjective experience. The idea that we can pin down the biological mechanisms of complex human thoughts, feelings and behaviors is part of the problem with our thinking in my view. We cannot do this now, and we have no indication that we will be able to do so in the futurea view put forward in critical neuroscience too, by the way (1-3). Second, if you give a drug that affects mechanisms P, Q, R, S and some others, and through its action produces an altered mental state in anyone who takes it regardless of diagnosis (allowing for individual variation, of course), you will get some impact on emotions, including feelings of anhedonia. This may involve mechanisms related to anhedonia, including your hypothetical mechanism X, but it may not, since any significant alteration of mental state and activity will affect emotions in some way. Now this is a drug-centered action, and this is what I propose is happening when we use psychiatric drugs.
We recognize the fact that psychoactive substances like alcohol and heroin change our mental states and can therefore interact with unwanted mental states and feelings. We talk of using alcohol to drown our sorrows, but we don t consider alcohol to be targeting the biological basis of misery in any specific way. When we recognize that psychiatric drugs have psychoactive properties, then we can start to understand what they are doing in people who suffer from mental health problems, and we can start to make a thorough and informed judgement about the pros and cons of using them.
Aftab: When you say The idea that we can pin down the biological mechanisms of complex human thoughts, feelings and behaviors is part of the problem with our thinking in my view. We cannot do this now, and we have no indication that we will be able to do so in the future, do you say that in an epistemological sense, that is, reflective of the limits of human knowledge and understanding, or do you say that in an ontological sense, that is, you don t think that complex human thoughts, feelings and behaviors are mediated by biological mechanisms? By mediate I mean here that biological mechanisms are part of the causal chain that eventually generates human thoughts and behaviors; I am not implying that human thoughts and behaviors can be reduced to or entirely explained by biological mechanisms.
Moncrieff: It depends what you mean by mediate. I think the Wittgenstinian scholar, Peter Hacker, puts this issue well. For Hacker, the mind is a set of capacities of the human organism (like Aristotle s psuche or psyche). The human brain working as a whole is necessary to generate these capacities, but individual mental processes cannot necessarily be pinned down to specific brain mechanisms. Think of emotional states like anger, elation, anxiety, and fear. They are all associated with increased adrenaline and other arousal mechanisms, but they have their own character, and this character derives from how the individual appraises their worldly situation, not from the nature of the biochemical or physiological reactions going on.
Aftab: You give the example of opioid medications as having disease centered effects as well as drug centered effects. Given that our understanding of causal mechanisms of serious mental illness as well as mechanisms of drug action is less than comprehensive, how do we know that such dual effects are not the case in at least some individuals with serious mental illness? Since that is an empirical matter, I don t think we can rule this possibility out on an a priori basis.
Moncrieff: There are many things we can t rule outthat doesn t mean they are useful ideas. The drug-centered model provides an adequate explanation of drug action in mental disorders. There is no need to postulate a hypothetical disease-centered action alongside it.
Aftab: What is your view of the philosophy of psychiatry literature that has emerged in recent decades, in great part thanks to British academics such as Bill Fulford and Tim Thornton? I m particularly thinking of the body of work that is devoted to questions of whether the boundary between "normal" and "pathological" can be drawn on the basis of objective, scientific facts, and what is the relationship between meaning and disease (Derek Bolton), and how to best understand and explain causal mechanisms in psychiatric conditions (Ken Kendler, Peter Zachar). This body of work seems to have great relevance to your interests; have you engaged with it in your writings?
Moncrieff: I have followed the work of Bill Fulford and to a lesser extent the others you mention in detail over the last few decades and I am about to have a paper published in the Journal Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology that responds to their work.4 However, I think it was Thomas Szasz, whom I met a couple of times in my life, who identified the main problem with psychiatry and few modern philosophers seem prepared to engage with his core arguments (with the exception of Bill Fulford).
For Szasz, there is a key distinction between a condition of the body and a situation that is characterized by self-directed, human behavior (as opposed to involuntary behavior caused by a biological process or event). In this, he follows anti-positivist philosophers, including the later Wittgenstein, who stress the differences between the natural world and the human world and how these entail different forms of knowledge. Szasz argues that psychiatry mostly deals with self-directed behavior and is therefore different from other parts of medicine that deal with bodily conditions.
Much of the psychiatric establishment clearly agrees with Szasz s distinction, because it wants to demonstrate that psychiatry too deals with bodiesor more specifically brainsand that psychiatric disorders are, in fact, brain diseases. I agree with both Szasz and the biological psychiatrists that it is important to know whether behavior is the direct result of a specific biological mechanism or not. However, I do not think research that finds a slightly higher rate of this or that biological feature in the brains of people with a psychiatric diagnosis compared to healthy controls demonstrates that mental disorders originate in the brain, as opposed to in the person s agency or character.
But I also don t think that the behavior that characterizes some mental disorders is quite the same as ordinary, fully volitional behavior, as Szasz suggests, either. The thinking and behavior characteristic of psychosis, for example, is not rational in a clear-cut way. People with psychosis do not respond to environmental cues and evidence in the way that people usually do, and their purposes are not easily and immediately discernible to other people. They may not have as much control over their behavior as people ordinarily do, either.
Although the behavior we associate with mental disorder is not simply the same as everyday behavior, I don t think it is distinct either. It is not a biological reflex, and therefore it can be viewed as part of the self or character, just as other, more clearly voluntary behavior is. This is why I refer to mental disorder as part of the range of ways in which human beings live within, and interact with, their world.4
Aftab: What about psychological experiences that are involuntary, unwanted, and distressing, such as auditory hallucinations and obsessions? At least in some instances, they are perceived by individuals to be intrusive and threatening to their sense of selves and lead to help-seeking behaviors. Do you also think of those experiences as parts of the self or reflective of the individual s values, desires, and intentions?
Moncrieff: This is a good question, and it highlights the complexity of our human nature, which I cannot do justice to here obviously. Certainly, some mental processes are not straightforwardly voluntary. Our moods and emotions, for example, are not brought on at our demand. Yet, although feelings are usually unbidden, we can nevertheless usually exercise some control over how we behave in response to them, and, often, with time and experience, over the feelings themselves. In the normal course of things, we see our moods and emotions as being part of ourselves or our character. As I put it in my recent paper the way we express our emotions is part of what is characteristic about us as individuals.4
I think many symptoms of mental disorders, including extreme or prolonged moods, but also obsessional thoughts and hallucinations, are of the same nature. People who end up in services may find their experiences difficult to resist and control, but that is true to some degree of many mental states and does not mean they are simply the meaningless byproducts of biological events.
Aftab: We know that psychosis can occur in conditions such as Parkinson disease and Alzheimer disease, and there are phenomenological similarities between psychosis in these instances and the psychosis experienced in schizophrenia. I assume you consider the former two to be diseases but the not the latter. If we were to restrict ourselves to examining the psychotic experiences only (without considering the concomitant presence of motor or cognitive symptoms), is there anything in the nature of these psychotic experiences that tells you whether they should be considered a disease or not?
Moncrieff: Physical states can occasionally mimic psychological ones. Thyroid hormone deficiency is famously said to cause depression. Often there are some phenomenological differences, but probably not always. Amphetamine abuse can cause psychosis. Again, there are some phenomenological differences if you were to look at a group level, but you cannot necessarily distinguish amphetamine-induced psychosis from an idiopathic psychotic episode in an individual patient on the basis of symptoms alone. However, this does not mean that the majority of instances of psychosis and depression are of the same nature.
As I have said before, many philosophers have pointed to how human emotions and mental states cannot be understood in a mechanical sense as isolated phenomena or events. They are intrinsically connected to the whole life history and experience of the individual, and the society in which that individual has grown up. Whereas thyroid deficiency may provide an adequate explanation of an episode of depression brought on by hypothyroidism, and thyroid hormone will usually provide an adequate treatment, a normal episode of depression has to be understood and treated in quite a different way, as a human reaction that requires a human-level response.
Aftab: You seem to suggest that if a behavior or experience can be seen as a meaningful response to personal experiences, environment trauma, social alienation, and so on, then it should not be considered the product of a brain disease (blogs here and here). Two questions. One, human minds are great at conjuring explanations of meaning where none may exist. How can we ensure that our attributions of meaning are not simply instances of creative storytelling? Second, there is no philosophical reason why meaning and biological abnormalities should be considered mutually exclusive. Someone who is experiencing paranoia as a result of cocaine use can still find that paranoia as imbued with meaning and distorted reason, but there is no denying that it was the result of a brain aberration. Your thoughts?
Moncrieff: We can never be sure about meaning. It is not a categorical thingthis is one of the many aspects in which the activity of human beings differs from the natural world and the form of our understanding needs to reflect this difference. Psychotherapy is premised on the idea that meaning is opaque and contested. The therapist s interpretation of feelings and events may be quite different from the subject s and this is not an arena where we can ever know the truth as we know it in physical science.
I take issue with your statement that there is no philosophical reason why meaning and biological abnormalities should be considered mutually exclusive, and I argue this point in detail in my recent philosophical paper.4 We are biological beings, and our behavior and activity is reflected in our biology, so of course meaning and biological abnormalities coexist. Yet, when we think of behavior, biological causation trumps meaning and agency. If an actiona twitch or a seizure, for exampleis caused by a biological process, this removes it from the realm of agency. It does not make sense to think of an action as both caused by a biological reflex and initiated by the self in an intentional fashion. They are mutually incompatible situations.
Biological processes are not meaningful, but biology is the context in which human agency takes place, and it sets the limits of possibility. People with intellectual disability, Alzheimer disease or other brain diseases may make meaningful choices, but their agency is circumscribed (as it is for all of us) by the nature of their brains. And so it is for those under the influence of substances. The biological limitations are not meaningful in themselves, but within these limits people may still be able to make choices and act in an intentional and meaningful fashion. However, the extent to which behavior is driven, changed or limited by a brain disease is not meaningful.
As I show in my recent philosophical paper, Szasz was trying to highlight how this distinction plays out in the difference between disease and behavior. Only when behavior is the product of a specific physical process, such as a brain tumor, can it be thought of as the symptom of a disease, and in this case, it is not meaningful. Otherwise it is part and parcel of the individual s character; it reflects the individual s values, desires and intentionsin other words it has meaning.
Aftab: When it comes to schizophrenia, a large body of research literature shows that there is a robust genetic component, that there are well-replicated associations with obstetrical complications, infections, inflammatory processes, cannabis use, and as a group, individuals with schizophrenia show differences in brain volume and cognitive functioning. I agree, there is no specific abnormality of brain structure or function, but there is a range of non-specific neurobiological factors which have been implicated as risk factors on a consistent basis. If schizophrenia was merely a problem in living or merely a different way of being human, why would we observe this risk factor profile in research studies?
Moncrieff: I would put it another way. Despite decades of extremely well-funded research, we have yet to identify any specific biological factor associated with any type of mental disorder, including schizophrenia. There is a genetic component to many things, and it is likely this includes some aspects of character or temperament that are associated with developing schizophrenia. As far as other research goes, despite what you and others say, findings are not well replicated and the research has failed to control for crucial confounding factors like drug treatment, social class, stress and IQ.
There are myriad reasons why people who show unusual behavior that is classified as schizophrenia are likely to have higher rates of obstetric complications, inflammatory markers, dopamine abnormalities, drug use etc. when compared to the sort of stable, employed, middle class people that become the normal controls in biological studies. The most consistent and well-replicated finding in people with schizophrenia is the evidence of smaller brain size and larger brain ventricles, yet after years of talk about schizophrenic brains, it transpires that this is, at least in large part, caused by antipsychotic drug treatment.
Aftab: To what extent are Szaszian or neo-Szasizan views on the nature of psychiatric disorders fundamental to the critical psychiatry movement? Are there folks who identify as critical psychiatrists and who agree with your views on psychopharmacology but disagree with your views on the nature of psychiatric disorders?
Moncrieff: Most people who identify as critical psychiatrists are not fans of Szasz, and I am sure there are many who accept my ideas about psychopharmacology without signing up to my Szasian critique of psychiatry. Individual critical psychiatrists have been influenced by many other thinkers and movements such as Foucault, Laing, Meyer, the service user movement, and the therapeutic community movement. I think there are commonalities among all these positions, but also something that is distinctive, and the critical psychiatry movement benefits from a dialogue between different perspectives.
Aftab: What do you see as the appropriate role and responsibility of psychiatrists within the medical profession and in society at large? How do you implement this vision in your own psychiatric practice, working in a system that largely doesn t share your ideas?
Moncrieff: As I have explained, I do not think the majority of the situations that psychiatrists help to manage are diseases or illnesses, or things that arise from the physical body. I think they are better understood as forms of behavior that are unusual, sometimes irrational and unpredictable, and socially problematic for one reason or another. I am not convinced therefore that it is logical for them to be regarded as part of the terrain of medicine.
However, that does not mean I don t think there is a job to be done. Many people find negotiating the demands of modern society difficult and need support of one sort or another. Some people behave in ways that disturb the peace and sometimes the safety of others, yet it would not be appropriate or possible to prosecute or punish them using the criminal law. I see psychiatry as a sort of social work service that is not essentially medical but has a medical component. The medical component concerns identifying the rare cases when a genuine medical (bodily) condition mimics a psychological state, and the use of drugs. As I have explained, I believe that some drugs can be useful in some situations, and clinical pharmacology expertise is essential to ensure they are used safely, only when necessary, and to resist pressure from Pharma and other quarters to use them more widely.
So in this sense I believe psychiatry is a fundamentally political activity. It is one of the informal social control apparatus that society has delegated to manage behavior that is socially problematic. Calling it a medical specialty disguises this fact and deprives people of the level of oversight and scrutiny that would be considered necessary if this was acknowledged. I think recognizing this fundamental aspect of psychiatry enables me to be transparent about what I do, which helps me to balance the interests of different parties as fairly as possible.
Aftab: Thank you!
The article in Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology referenced by Dr Moncrieff was in press at the time this interview was conducted but has since been published online. Readers may be interested in additional critical reflections on the paper in my blog post here. I d also like to add that there is a large body of literature critically engaging with the ideas of Thomas Szasz, such as the 2019 book Thomas Szasz: An Appraisal of His Legacy (International Perspectives in Philosophy and Psychiatry), which I would encourage readers to explore.
The opinions expressed in the interviews are those of the participants and do not necessarily reflect the opinions of Psychiatric Times.
Previously in Conversations in Critical Psychiatry
Relentless Warrior for Mental Health: Allen Frances, MD
The Structure of Psychiatric Revolutions: Anne Harrington, DPhil
Skepticism of the Gentle Variety: Derek Bolton, PhD
Explanatory Methods in Psychiatry: The Importance of Perspectives: Paul R. McHugh, MD
Chaos Theory with a Human Face: Niall McLaren, MBBS, FRANZCP
The Rise and Fall of Pragmatism in Psychiatry: S. Nassir Ghaemi, MD, MPH
Integrating Academic Inquiry and Reformist Activism in Psychiatry: Sandra Steingard, MD, and G. Scott Waterman, MD
Social Constructionism Meets Aging and Dementia: Peter Whitehouse, MD, PhD
50 Shades of Misdiagnosis: Susannah Cahalan
Institutional Corruption and Social Justice in Psychiatry: Lisa Cosgrove, PhD
The Impoverishment of Psychiatric Knowledge: Giovanni Fava, MD
Follow this link:
Psychiatry and the Human Condition: Joanna Moncrieff, MD - Psychiatric Times
- Human behavior is driven by fifteen key motives - Earth.com - February 25th, 2025 [February 25th, 2025]
- Nature Human Behavior is back, this time touting allyship - Why Evolution Is True - February 25th, 2025 [February 25th, 2025]
- 30 Times Courtrooms Became The Stage For The Strangest Human Behavior - Bored Panda - February 3rd, 2025 [February 3rd, 2025]
- The Impact of AI on Human Behavior: Insights and Implications - iTMunch - January 23rd, 2025 [January 23rd, 2025]
- Disturbing Wildlife Isnt Fun: IFS Parveen Kaswan Raises Concern Over Human Behavior in Viral Clip - Indian Masterminds - January 15th, 2025 [January 15th, 2025]
- The interplay of time and space in human behavior: a sociological perspective on the TSCH model - Nature.com - January 1st, 2025 [January 1st, 2025]
- Thinking Slowly: The Paradoxical Slowness of Human Behavior - Caltech - December 23rd, 2024 [December 23rd, 2024]
- From smog to crime: How air pollution is shaping human behavior and public safety - The Times of India - December 9th, 2024 [December 9th, 2024]
- The Smell Of Death Has A Strange Influence On Human Behavior - IFLScience - October 26th, 2024 [October 26th, 2024]
- "WEIRD" in psychology literature oversimplifies the global diversity of human behavior. - Psychology Today - October 2nd, 2024 [October 2nd, 2024]
- Scientists issue warning about increasingly alarming whale behavior due to human activity - Orcasonian - September 23rd, 2024 [September 23rd, 2024]
- Does AI adoption call for a change in human behavior? - Fast Company - July 26th, 2024 [July 26th, 2024]
- Dogs can smell human stress and it alters their own behavior, study reveals - New York Post - July 26th, 2024 [July 26th, 2024]
- Trajectories of brain and behaviour development in the womb, at birth and through infancy - Nature.com - June 18th, 2024 [June 18th, 2024]
- AI model predicts human behavior from our poor decision-making - Big Think - June 18th, 2024 [June 18th, 2024]
- ZkSync defends Sybil measures as Binance offers own ZK token airdrop - TradingView - June 18th, 2024 [June 18th, 2024]
- On TikTok, Goldendoodles Are People Trapped in Dog Bodies - The New York Times - June 18th, 2024 [June 18th, 2024]
- 10 things only introverts find irritating, according to psychology - Hack Spirit - June 18th, 2024 [June 18th, 2024]
- 32 animals that act weirdly human sometimes - Livescience.com - May 24th, 2024 [May 24th, 2024]
- NBC Is Using Animals To Push The LGBT Agenda. Here Are 5 Abhorrent Animal Behaviors Humans Shouldn't Emulate - The Daily Wire - May 24th, 2024 [May 24th, 2024]
- New study examines the dynamics of adaptive autonomy in human volition and behavior - PsyPost - May 24th, 2024 [May 24th, 2024]
- 30000 years of history reveals that hard times boost human societies' resilience - Livescience.com - May 12th, 2024 [May 12th, 2024]
- Kingdom of the Planet of the Apes Actors Had Trouble Reverting Back to Human - CBR - May 12th, 2024 [May 12th, 2024]
- The need to feel safe is a core driver of human behavior. - Psychology Today - April 15th, 2024 [April 15th, 2024]
- AI learned how to sway humans by watching a cooperative cooking game - Science News Magazine - March 29th, 2024 [March 29th, 2024]
- We can't combat climate change without changing minds. This psychology class explores how. - Northeastern University - March 11th, 2024 [March 11th, 2024]
- Bees Reveal a Human-Like Collective Intelligence We Never Knew Existed - ScienceAlert - March 11th, 2024 [March 11th, 2024]
- Franciscan AI expert warns of technology becoming a 'pseudo-religion' - Detroit Catholic - March 11th, 2024 [March 11th, 2024]
- Freshwater resources at risk thanks to human behavior - messenger-inquirer - March 11th, 2024 [March 11th, 2024]
- Astrocytes Play Critical Role in Regulating Behavior - Neuroscience News - March 11th, 2024 [March 11th, 2024]
- Freshwater resources at risk thanks to human behavior - Sunnyside Sun - March 11th, 2024 [March 11th, 2024]
- Freshwater resources at risk thanks to human behavior - Blue Mountain Eagle - March 11th, 2024 [March 11th, 2024]
- 7 Books on Human Behavior - Times Now - March 11th, 2024 [March 11th, 2024]
- Euphemisms increasingly used to soften behavior that would be questionable in direct language - Norfolk Daily News - February 29th, 2024 [February 29th, 2024]
- Linking environmental influences, genetic research to address concerns of genetic determinism of human behavior - Phys.org - February 29th, 2024 [February 29th, 2024]
- Emerson's Insight: Navigating the Three Fundamental Desires of Human Nature - The Good Men Project - February 29th, 2024 [February 29th, 2024]
- Dogs can recognize a bad person and there's science to prove it. - GOOD - February 29th, 2024 [February 29th, 2024]
- What Is Organizational Behavior? Everything You Need To Know - MarketWatch - February 4th, 2024 [February 4th, 2024]
- Overcoming 'Otherness' in Scientific Research Commentary in Nature Human Behavior USA - English - USA - PR Newswire - February 4th, 2024 [February 4th, 2024]
- "Reichman University's behavioral economics program: Navigating human be - The Jerusalem Post - January 19th, 2024 [January 19th, 2024]
- Of trees, symbols of humankind, on Tu BShevat - The Jewish Star - January 19th, 2024 [January 19th, 2024]
- Tapping Into The Power Of Positive Psychology With Acclaimed Expert Niyc Pidgeon - GirlTalkHQ - January 19th, 2024 [January 19th, 2024]
- Don't just make resolutions, 'be the architect of your future self,' says Stanford-trained human behavior expert - CNBC - December 31st, 2023 [December 31st, 2023]
- Never happy? Humans tend to imagine how life could be better : Short Wave - NPR - December 31st, 2023 [December 31st, 2023]
- People who feel unhappy but hide it well usually exhibit these 9 behaviors - Hack Spirit - December 31st, 2023 [December 31st, 2023]
- If you display these 9 behaviors, you're being passive aggressive without realizing it - Hack Spirit - December 31st, 2023 [December 31st, 2023]
- Men who are relationship-oriented by nature usually display these 9 behaviors - Hack Spirit - December 31st, 2023 [December 31st, 2023]
- A look at the curious 'winter break' behavior of ChatGPT-4 - ReadWrite - December 14th, 2023 [December 14th, 2023]
- Neuroscience and Behavior Major (B.S.) | College of Liberal Arts - UNH's College of Liberal Arts - December 14th, 2023 [December 14th, 2023]
- The positive health effects of prosocial behaviors | News | Harvard ... - HSPH News - October 27th, 2023 [October 27th, 2023]
- The valuable link between succession planning and skills - Human Resource Executive - October 27th, 2023 [October 27th, 2023]
- Okinawa's ants show reduced seasonal behavior in areas with more human development - Phys.org - October 27th, 2023 [October 27th, 2023]
- How humans use their sense of smell to find their way | Penn Today - Penn Today - October 27th, 2023 [October 27th, 2023]
- Wrestling With Evil in the World, or Is It Something Else? - Psychiatric Times - October 27th, 2023 [October 27th, 2023]
- Shimmying like electric fish is a universal movement across species - Earth.com - October 27th, 2023 [October 27th, 2023]
- Why do dogs get the zoomies? - Care.com - October 27th, 2023 [October 27th, 2023]
- How Stuart Robinson's misconduct went overlooked for years - Washington Square News - October 27th, 2023 [October 27th, 2023]
- Whatchamacolumn: Homeless camps back in the news - News-Register - October 27th, 2023 [October 27th, 2023]
- Stunted Growth in Infants Reshapes Brain Function and Cognitive ... - Neuroscience News - October 27th, 2023 [October 27th, 2023]
- Social medias role in modeling human behavior, societies - kuwaittimes - October 27th, 2023 [October 27th, 2023]
- The gift of reformation - Living Lutheran - October 27th, 2023 [October 27th, 2023]
- After pandemic, birds are surprisingly becoming less fearful of humans - Study Finds - October 27th, 2023 [October 27th, 2023]
- Nick Treglia: The trouble with fairness and the search for truth - 1819 News - October 27th, 2023 [October 27th, 2023]
- Science has an answer for why people still wave on Zoom - Press Herald - October 27th, 2023 [October 27th, 2023]
- Orcas are learning terrifying new behaviors. Are they getting smarter? - Livescience.com - October 27th, 2023 [October 27th, 2023]
- Augmenting the Regulatory Worker: Are We Making Them Better or ... - BioSpace - October 27th, 2023 [October 27th, 2023]
- What "The Creator", a film about the future, tells us about the present - InCyber - October 27th, 2023 [October 27th, 2023]
- WashU Expert: Some parasites turn hosts into 'zombies' - The ... - Washington University in St. Louis - October 27th, 2023 [October 27th, 2023]
- Is secondhand smoke from vapes less toxic than from traditional ... - Missouri S&T News and Research - October 27th, 2023 [October 27th, 2023]
- How apocalyptic cults use psychological tricks to brainwash their ... - Big Think - October 27th, 2023 [October 27th, 2023]
- Human action pushing the world closer to environmental tipping ... - Morung Express - October 27th, 2023 [October 27th, 2023]
- What We Get When We Give | Harvard Medicine Magazine - Harvard University - October 27th, 2023 [October 27th, 2023]
- Psychological Anime: 12 Series You Should Watch - But Why Tho? - October 27th, 2023 [October 27th, 2023]
- Roosters May Recognize Their Reflections in Mirrors, Study Suggests - Smithsonian Magazine - October 27th, 2023 [October 27th, 2023]
- June 30 Zodiac: Sign, Traits, Compatibility and More - AZ Animals - May 13th, 2023 [May 13th, 2023]
- Indiana's Funding Ban for Kinsey Sex-Research Institute Threatens ... - The Chronicle of Higher Education - May 13th, 2023 [May 13th, 2023]
- Have AI Chatbots Developed Theory of Mind? What We Do and Do ... - The New York Times - March 31st, 2023 [March 31st, 2023]
- Scoop: Coming Up on a New Episode of HOUSEBROKEN on FOX ... - Broadway World - March 31st, 2023 [March 31st, 2023]
- Here's five fall 2023 classes to fire up your bookbag - Duke Chronicle - March 31st, 2023 [March 31st, 2023]
- McDonald: Aspen's like living in a 'Pullman town' - The Aspen Times - March 31st, 2023 [March 31st, 2023]